Book 8 / Chapter 10

Paragraph 2 - Analogies to Political Constitutions in the Household

Explanation - Part By Part

Part 1
Original Text:

"One may find resemblances to the constitutions and, as it were, patterns of them even in households."

Aristotle is suggesting that the structure of a household can reflect, on a smaller scale, the various types of government. Just as cities and nations are organized under different constitutions, households also have internal dynamics and relationships that mirror these governing systems. These relationships offer "patterns" or parallels to larger political structures, making the household a microcosm of political life.

Part 2
Original Text:

"For the association of a father with his sons bears the form of monarchy, since the father cares for his children; and this is why Homer calls Zeus 'father'; it is the ideal of monarchy to be paternal rule."

Aristotle is making a connection here between political systems and relationships within a family. He compares a father's relationship with his children to a monarchy because, like a king, the father takes on the role of guiding and caring for his "subjects" (his children) with their well-being in mind. Aristotle notes that this type of rule is ideally paternal—meaning it reflects the care and responsibility of a fatherly figure rather than simply dominance or exploitation. This is why Homer, the ancient poet, refers to Zeus (the king of the gods in Greek mythology) as "father"—because Zeus embodies the protective, guiding role expected of a good king in a monarchy. The underlying point Aristotle seems to be making is that the best kind of monarch rules out of concern for the people, much like a father cares for his family.

Part 3
Original Text:

"But among the Persians the rule of the father is tyrannical; they use their sons as slaves."

Aristotle is drawing a contrast between different forms of familial rule and comparing them to political systems. In this part, he criticizes the way Persian fathers treat their sons, likening it to tyranny. Instead of a fatherly care that seeks the well-being of the children (as in the ideal form of monarchy), Persian fathers, according to Aristotle, treat their sons as if they are slaves—serving the father's own interests rather than nurturing or guiding the children. This, to Aristotle, reflects a corruption of the natural and proper relationship between a father and his children, much like how tyranny is a corruption of monarchy in politics.

The key point here is that parental authority is supposed to resemble a form of "good rule" that benefits those being ruled (the children), but when that authority devolves into oppressive self-interest, it mirrors the way tyrants govern.

Part 4
Original Text:

"Tyrannical too is the rule of a master over slaves; for it is the advantage of the master that is brought about in it."

Here, Aristotle is pointing out that the rule of a master over slaves is inherently tyrannical because it serves only the master's advantage and interests, not the well-being of the slaves. This dynamic mirrors tyranny in a political setting, where the ruler prioritizes power and personal benefit over the collective welfare of the people. Aristotle seems to suggest that such an arrangement is self-centered and lacks the mutual benefit or care that would characterize a more just and ethical relationship.

Part 5
Original Text:

"Now this seems to be a correct form of government, but the Persian type is perverted; for the modes of rule appropriate to different relations are diverse."

In this part, Aristotle is making a distinction between what might appear to be proper or natural governance and its distorted forms. He argues that in certain relationships, such as the rule of a master over slaves or a father over his children, there is, in theory, a "correct" way of exercising authority. However, the Persians, in his view, distort this natural order. They transform what could be a caring, paternal form of rule (as seen in monarchy) into something oppressive and exploitative (resembling tyranny) by treating their children as slaves.

The broader point Aristotle emphasizes here is that different relationships require different kinds of authority, and mismatched or excessive forms of control disrupt the natural balance of those relationships. When the "mode of rule" is inappropriate for the context—such as paternal authority becoming tyrannical—it becomes a perversion of what governance should ideally be.

Part 6
Original Text:

"The association of man and wife seems to be aristocratic; for the man rules in accordance with his worth, and in those matters in which a man should rule, but the matters that befit a woman he hands over to her."

Here, Aristotle compares the relationship between a husband and wife to an aristocracy. In his view, an aristocracy is a system where leadership is based on merit or "worth." Similarly, Aristotle suggests that the husband rules the household in areas where he is supposedly more capable or suited, while the wife is responsible for matters that are considered her domain or expertise. Essentially, he is describing a division of responsibilities in which each partner has their designated roles based on what he assumes are their innate or societal strengths.

It is important to note that this perspective is deeply reflective of the cultural norms and gender roles of ancient Greece, where men were often positioned as authority figures and women were assigned domestic responsibilities. This idea may not align with modern understandings of equality and shared decision-making in relationships, but it provides insight into how Aristotle saw hierarchy and roles in familial structures as mirroring political systems.

Part 7
Original Text:

"If the man rules in everything the relation passes over into oligarchy; for in doing so he is not acting in accordance with their respective worth, and not ruling in virtue of his superiority."

Here, Aristotle is analyzing the dynamics of a household and comparing them to different political systems. He says that in an ideal household, the man and woman each have their respective roles, and the man should take leadership in areas where he is more capable or suited, while allowing the woman to lead in areas where her abilities are more appropriate. This is akin to aristocracy, where leadership is based on merit or worth.

However, if the man insists on controlling everything, disregarding the abilities or contributions of his wife, this turns into something resembling an oligarchy. In oligarchy, power is concentrated in the hands of a few, not because they deserve it through excellence, but often because of wealth, privilege, or brute control. Similarly, a man dominating every aspect of the household isn't leading based on merit or mutual respect but rather arbitrarily or selfishly, ignoring the partnership's balance. This, Aristotle implies, is an imbalance or corruption of how relationships ideally should work.

Part 8
Original Text:

"Sometimes, however, women rule, because they are heiresses; so their rule is not in virtue of excellence but due to wealth and power, as in oligarchies."

In this part, Aristotle is making a comparison between a household and forms of government. Specifically, he observes that in some households, women may hold authority or "rule" because they are heiresses—meaning they inherit wealth or power. However, their rule, according to Aristotle, is not based on personal virtue or excellence (arete, a key concept in his philosophy, meaning moral excellence or merit). Instead, their authority comes from external factors like wealth or inheritance, much like how rulers in an oligarchy gain and maintain their power due to wealth rather than virtue or merit.

This is Aristotle's way of noting that when authority arises from external power (like money) rather than inherent moral or intellectual superiority, it mirrors the dynamics of an oligarchy, which is structured around the control of a few wealthy individuals.

Part 9
Original Text:

"The association of brothers is like timocracy; for they are equal, except in so far as they differ in age; hence if they differ much in age, the friendship is no longer of the fraternal type."

Aristotle is making an analogy here, comparing the dynamic among brothers to a form of political constitution known as timocracy. In a timocracy, people are generally considered equal, except for certain qualifications (like property or merit). Similarly, brothers are largely seen as equals within a family, but there can be some differences — most notably in age. If the age gap is significant, Aristotle notes, it undermines the sense of equality and changes the kind of relationship they share. In essence, the "fraternity" or balance of their bond depends on the degree of equality they can maintain, much like the functioning of timocracy as a political system hinges on a shared standard among its members.

Part 10
Original Text:

"Democracy is found chiefly in masterless dwellings (for here every one is on an equality), and in those in which the ruler is weak and every one has licence to do as he pleases."

Here, Aristotle is making a comparison between democracy as a political system and certain types of households or living situations. In a democracy, the core idea is equality among people, where no single person has excessive control over others and everyone has the freedom to act as they wish. Aristotle relates this to what he calls "masterless dwellings," which are homes or households without a strong central figure (a "master") in charge. In such a situation, everyone is essentially on the same level, and because there is no clear authority, individuals can act however they please. Similarly, in a democratic government, the power is equally distributed, and there is less emphasis on hierarchy or strong rulers—sometimes to the extent that order can become difficult to maintain if the governing authority is too weak.