Book 3 / Chapter 6
Paragraph 1 - The Nature of True Bravery
Explanation - Part By Part
"That it is a mean with regard to feelings of fear and confidence has already been made evident; and plainly the things we fear are terrible things, and these are, to speak without qualification, evils; for which reason people even define fear as expectation of evil."
Aristotle begins by reminding us that courage is about finding a balanced "middle ground" when it comes to our feelings of fear and confidence. He says that the things we fear are naturally things that are "terrible" or bad—what he simply calls "evils." Fear, in itself, is the anticipation or expectation of encountering something harmful or negative. In other words, fear arises when we think something bad is likely to happen. This sets the stage for Aristotle to explore what kinds of fears are appropriate and how courage plays a role in managing them.
"Now we fear all evils, e.g. disgrace, poverty, disease, friendlessness, death, but the brave man is not thought to be concerned with all; for to fear some things is even right and noble, and it is base not to fear them- e.g. disgrace; he who fears this is good and modest, and he who does not is shameless."
Aristotle is discussing the nature of courage and emphasizing that not all fears are the same, and not all are inappropriate or cowardly. Some fears are completely justifiable and even appropriate for decent and honorable people, like the fear of disgrace. Fear of disgrace, in this case, reflects personal virtue—showing that someone has a sense of honor, decency, and a moral compass. On the other hand, a person who doesn't fear disgrace or shame lacks this moral sensitivity and is considered shameless, which Aristotle views as dishonorable and "base."
Essentially, Aristotle is highlighting that being brave doesn't mean being indifferent to all fears—some fears (like disgrace) are a sign of good character. Courage is not the absence of fear but the ability to navigate and judge which fears are worth enduring and which deserve respect.
"He is, however, by some people called brave, by a transference of the word to a new meaning; for he has in him something which is like the brave man, since the brave man also is a fearless person."
Aristotle is pointing out that people sometimes use the term "brave" in a loose or metaphorical way to describe someone who is fearless, even if their fearlessness doesn’t align with what true bravery entails. This happens because there’s a similarity: bravery involves fearlessness, so we might mistakenly label someone as brave simply because they lack fear in certain situations. However, Aristotle suggests that true bravery isn’t just about being fearless; it’s about facing fear for the right reasons, in the right circumstances, and especially in situations where enduring fear or danger is noble or virtuous.
"Poverty and disease we perhaps ought not to fear, nor in general the things that do not proceed from vice and are not due to a man himself. But not even the man who is fearless of these is brave. Yet we apply the word to him also in virtue of a similarity; for some who in the dangers of war are cowards are liberal and are confident in face of the loss of money."
Aristotle is making a distinction here about what true courage is. He argues that we shouldn't fear things like poverty or disease—because these conditions are not moral failings (they don’t arise from a person's bad choices, faults, or vices). However, just because someone doesn’t fear these situations, it doesn’t automatically make them truly brave in the ethical sense.
For example, a person who can face financial difficulty (like losing money) with confidence might be considered "brave" in a loose or figurative sense, but this is not the same as the deeper, moral courage Aristotle is exploring. He points out that some people who display this fearlessness regarding money might still be cowards in dangerous situations like war. This serves to highlight that bravery isn’t just about being unafraid of certain challenges—it’s about how one responds to specific, noble, and morally significant dangers.
"Nor is a man a coward if he fears insult to his wife and children or envy or anything of the kind; nor brave if he is confident when he is about to be flogged."
Aristotle is addressing the nuanced way we attribute courage or cowardice to people. Here, he argues that fearing certain things—like harm to one’s family or envy from others—does not make someone a coward. These are natural and justified fears, tied to values or responsibilities. Similarly, a person who shows confidence or fearlessness in situations like being physically punished (e.g., flogged) is not necessarily brave.
Why? Because bravery isn’t just about facing any situation without fear; it’s about confronting truly important, significant dangers, such as those involving noble stakes—like death in battle or great moral tests. Being fearless in trivial or inappropriate contexts doesn’t make someone truly brave; it must involve a readiness to face the right kinds of challenges for the right reasons.
"With what sort of terrible things, then, is the brave man concerned? Surely with the greatest; for no one is more likely than he to stand his ground against what is awe-inspiring."
Aristotle is exploring what specifically distinguishes the truly brave person. He explains that bravery is demonstrated in facing the most significant and terrifying challenges—those that inspire awe or dread because of their magnitude. A brave person isn’t someone who avoids fear altogether but rather someone who remains steadfast and composed in the face of life’s most profound, overwhelming threats, particularly when doing so requires extraordinary courage and moral strength. Aristotle implies that bravery involves meeting what is genuinely fearsome, rather than trivial dangers, with resolve.
"Now death is the most terrible of all things; for it is the end, and nothing is thought to be any longer either good or bad for the dead."
Aristotle is emphasizing that death is universally regarded as the most fearsome thing because it represents the ultimate endpoint of life. Once someone dies, they are no longer able to experience anything—be it good or bad—since they no longer exist as living beings capable of perception or action. This makes death uniquely final and, therefore, deeply terrifying to most people. It's this finality that underpins why it is viewed as the greatest of all "terrible things."
"But the brave man would not seem to be concerned even with death in all circumstances, e.g. at sea or in disease."
Aristotle points out that bravery isn’t about confronting death in every situation. For example, dying at sea or from an illness doesn’t necessarily involve the kind of courage that defines the virtue of bravery. These types of death lack a noble context—there's no purposeful action or greater cause tied to enduring these situations. Bravery, in Aristotle's view, is more connected to facing death in scenarios where honor or a higher purpose is at stake, rather than succumbing to circumstances that are beyond one's control or don't allow for meaningful action.
"In what circumstances, then? Surely in the noblest. Now such deaths are those in battle; for these take place in the greatest and noblest danger. And these are correspondingly honoured in city-states and at the courts of monarchs."
Aristotle is exploring what type of danger or circumstance best demonstrates true courage, and he concludes that it must be something noble. He highlights death in battle as the clearest example because it involves the greatest and most dignified type of risk—facing danger for the sake of others, such as one's community or country. This aligns with what societies in his time (like Greek city-states or royal courts) considered the most honorable and admirable form of courage; people celebrated and recognized such bravery publicly. Essentially, Aristotle sees courage as most genuine and praiseworthy when it's tied to honorable causes, especially when someone willingly faces great dangers that demand personal sacrifice.
"Properly, then, he will be called brave who is fearless in face of a noble death, and of all emergencies that involve death; and the emergencies of war are in the highest degree of this kind."
Here, Aristotle defines true bravery as the ability to remain fearless when faced with the possibility of a noble death—a death that occurs in circumstances that reflect honor and virtue. He views such bravery as most evident in situations of war, where the stakes and dangers are at their highest, involving not just personal survival but also courage for a greater cause, such as defending one’s community or principles. In these contexts, bravery is not about recklessness or fearlessness for trivial reasons; it’s about confronting fear and danger in service of something meaningful and morally significant.
"Yet at sea also, and in disease, the brave man is fearless, but not in the same way as the seaman; for he has given up hope of safety, and is disliking the thought of death in this shape, while they are hopeful because of their experience."
In this part, Aristotle is exploring how courage shows up differently depending on the situation. He points out that even a brave person can face death at sea or in illness without the same outlook as, say, a sailor. The reason? The brave person may be fearless, but they also feel a deep sense of dread or dislike for the kind of death they might face in such situations. On the other hand, sailors—because of their experience and skills—are able to hold on to hope for survival, even in dangerous circumstances. This distinction highlights that bravery isn't about blind fearlessness; it's about how one faces threats with reason, even when the odds or context feel grim.
"At the same time, we show courage in situations where there is the opportunity of showing prowess or where death is noble; but in these forms of death neither of these conditions is fulfilled."
Aristotle is highlighting the idea that true courage involves facing situations where one has the chance to demonstrate virtue or excellence (prowess) or where facing death is considered honorable or noble. In contrast, situations like dying from sickness or at sea (perhaps in a storm or accident) lack those elements. In such cases, there's no real opportunity to showcase personal bravery or to meet an honorable end, as these scenarios might seem more out of one’s control or lacking a noble purpose. Courage, for Aristotle, shines when the stakes involve both great danger and the potential to display moral strength or virtuous character, especially in contexts like war.